1 Can you tell us a little about your personal history? What brought you to Marxist philosophy?
In 1948, when I was 30, I became a teacher of
philosophy and joined the PCF. Philosophy was an interest; I was trying
to make it my profession. Politics was a passion; I was trying to become
a Communist militant.
My interest in philosophy was aroused by materialism and its critical function: for scientific knowledge, against all the mystifications of ideological
‘knowledge’. Against the merely moral denunciation of myths and lies,
for their rational and rigorous criticism. My passion for politics was
inspired by the revolutionary instinct, intelligence, courage and
heroism of the working class in its struggle for socialism. The War and
the long years of captivity had brought me into living contact with
workers and peasants, and acquainted me with Communist militants.
It was politics which decided everything. Not politics in general: Marxist-Leninist politics.
First I had to find them and understand them. That is
always extremely difficult for an intellectual. It was just as
difficult in the fifties and sixties, for reasons with which you are
familiar: the consequences of the ‘cult’, the Twentieth Congress, then
the crisis of the international Communist Movement. Above all, it was
not easy to resist the spread of contemporary ‘humanist’ ideology, and
bourgeois ideology’s other assaults on Marxism.
Once I had a better understanding of Marxist-Leninist
politics, I began to have a passion for philosophy too, for at last I
began to understand the great thesis of Marx, Lenin and Gramsci: that
philosophy is fundamentally political.
Everything that I have written, at first alone, later
in collaboration with younger comrades and friends, revolves, despite
the ‘abstraction’ of our essays, around these very concrete questions.
2 Can you be more precise: why is it generally so difficult to be a Communist in philosophy?
To be a Communist in philosophy is to become a partisan and artisan of Marxist-Leninist philosophy: of dialectical materialism.
It is not easy to become a Marxist-Leninist
philosopher. Like every ‘intellectual’, a philosophy teacher is a petty
bourgeois. When he opens his mouth, it is petty-bourgeois ideology that
speaks: its resources and ruses are infinite.
You know what Lenin says about ‘intellectuals’. Individually certain of them may (politically) be declared revolutionaries, and courageous ones. But as a mass, they remain ‘incorrigibly’ petty-bourgeois
in ideology. Gorky himself was, for Lenin, who admired his talents, a
petty-bourgeois revolutionary. To become ‘ideologists of the working
class’ (Lenin), ‘organic intellectuals’ of the proletariat (Gramsci),
intellectuals have to carry out a radical revolution in their ideas: a
long, painful and difficult re-education. An endless external and internal struggle.
Proletarians have a ‘class instinct’ which helps them
on the way to proletarian ‘class positions’. Intellectuals, on the
contrary, have a petty-bourgeois class instinct which fiercely resists
this transition.
A proletarian class position is more than a mere proletarian ‘class instinct’. It is the consciousness and practice which conform with the objective
reality of the proletarian class struggle. Class instinct is subjective
and spontaneous. Class position is objective and rational. To arrive at
proletarian class positions, the class instinct of proletarians only
needs to be educated ; the class instinct of the petty bourgeoisie, and hence of intellectuals, has, on the contrary, to be revolutionized.
This education and this revolution are, in the last analysis,
determined by proletarian class struggle conducted on the basis of the
principles of Marxist-Leninist theory.
As the Communist Manifesto says, knowledge of this theory can help certain intellectuals to go over to working class positions.
Marxist-Leninist theory includes a science (historical materialism) and a philosophy (dialectical materialism).
Marxist-Leninist philosophy is therefore one of the two theoretical
weapons indispensable to the class struggle of the proletariat.
Communist militants must assimilate and use the principles of the
theory: science and philosophy. The proletarian revolution needs
militants who are both scientists (historical materialism) and
philosophers (dialectical materialism) to assist in the defence and
development of theory.
The formation of these philosophers runs up against two great difficulties.
A first – political – difficulty. A
professional philosopher who joins the Party remains, ideologically, a
petty bourgeois. He must revolutionize his thought in order to occupy a
proletarian class position in philosophy.
This political difficulty is ‘determinant in the last instance’.
A second – theoretical – difficulty. We know in what direction and with what principles we must work in order to define this class position in philosophy.
But we must develop Marxist philosophy: it is theoretically and
politically urgent to do so. Now, this work is vast and difficult. For
in Marxist theory, philosophy has lagged behind the science of history.
Today, in our countries, this is the ‘dominant’ difficulty.
3 You therefore distinguish between a science
and a philosophy in Marxist theory? As you know, this distinction is
often contested today.
I know. But this ‘contestation’ is an old story.
To be extremely schematic, it may be said that, in
the history of the Marxist movement, the suppression of this distinction
has expressed either a rightist or a leftist deviation. The rightist
deviation suppresses philosophy: only science is left (positivism). The
leftist deviation suppresses science: only philosophy is left
(subjectivism). There are ‘exceptions’ to this (cases of ‘inversion’),
but they ‘confirm’ the rule.
The great leaders of the Marxist Workers’ Movement
from Marx and Engels to today have always said: these deviations are the
result of the influence and domination of bourgeois ideology over
Marxism. For their part, they always defended the distinction (science,
philosophy), not only for theoretical, but also for vital political
reasons. Think of Lenin in Materialism and Empirio-criticism or ‘Left-Wing’ Communism. His reasons are blindingly obvious.
4 How do you justify this distinction between science and philosophy in Marxist theory?
I shall answer you by formulating a number of provisional and schematic theses.
1. The fusion of Marxist theory and the Workers’
Movement is the most important event in the whole history of the class
struggle, i.e. in practically the whole of human history (first effects: the socialist revolutions).
2. Marxist theory (science and philosophy) represents an unprecedented revolution in the history of human knowledge.
3. Marx founded a new science: the science of
history. Let me use an image. The sciences we are familiar with have
been installed in a number of great ‘continents’. Before Marx, two such
continents had been opened up to scientific knowledge: the continent of
Mathematics and the continent of Physics. The first by the Greeks
(Thales), the second by Galileo. Marx opened up a third continent to
scientific knowledge: the continent of History.
4. The opening up of this new continent has induced a
revolution in philosophy. That is a law: philosophy is always linked to
the sciences.
Philosophy was born (with Plato) at the opening up of
the continent of Mathematics. It was transformed (with Descartes) by
the opening up of the continent of Physics. Today it is being
revolutionized by the opening up of the continent of History by Marx.
This revolution is called dialectical materialism.
Transformations of philosophy are always rebounds from great scientific discoveries. Hence in essentials, they arise after the event.
That is why philosophy has lagged behind science in Marxist theory.
There are other reasons which we all know about. But at present this is
the dominant one.
5. As a mass, only proletarian militants have
recognized the revolutionary scope of Marx’s scientific
discovery. Their
political practice has been transformed by it.
And here we come to the greatest theoretical scandal in contemporary history.
As a mass, the intellectuals, on the contrary, even
those whose ‘professional’ concern it is (specialists in the human
sciences, philosophers), have not really recognized, or have refused to
recognize, the unprecedented scope of Marx’s scientific discovery, which
they have condemned and despised, and which they distort when they do
discuss it.
With a few exceptions, they are still
‘dabbling’ in political economy, sociology, ethnology, ‘anthropology’,
‘social psychology’, etc., etc...., even today, one hundred years after Capital, just as some Aristotelian physicists were still ‘dabbling’ in physics, fifty years after
Galileo. Their ‘theories’ are ideological anachronisms, rejuvenated
with a large dose of intellectual subtleties and ultra-modern
mathematical techniques.
But this theoretical scandal is not a scandal at all.
It is an effect of the ideological class struggle: for it is bourgeois
ideology, bourgeois ‘culture’ which is in power, which exercises
‘hegemony’. As a mass, the intellectuals, including many Communist and
Marxist intellectuals, are, with exceptions, dominated in their theories by bourgeois ideology. With exceptions, the same thing happens in the ‘human’ sciences.
6. The same scandalous situation in philosophy. Who
has understood the astounding philosophical revolution induced by Marx’s
discovery? Only proletarian militants and leaders. As a mass, on the
contrary, professional philosophers have not even suspected it. When
they mention Marx it is always, with extremely rare exceptions, to
attack him, to condemn him, to ‘absorb’ him, to exploit him or to revise him.
Those, like Engels and Lenin, who have defended
dialectical materialism, are treated as philosophically insignificant.
The real scandal is that certain Marxist philosophers have succumbed to
the same infection, in the name of ‘anti-dogmatism’. But here, too, the
reason is the same: the effect of the ideological class struggle. For it
is bourgeois ideology, bourgeois ‘culture’, which is in power.
7. The crucial tasks of the Communist movement in theory :
– to recognize and know the revolutionary theoretical scope of Marxist-Leninist science and philosophy;
– to struggle against the bourgeois and
petty-bourgeois world outlook which always threatens Marxist theory, and
which deeply impregnates it today. The general form of this world outlook: Economism (today ‘technocracy’) and its ‘spiritual complement’ Ethical Idealism
(today ‘Humanism’). Economism and Ethical Idealism have constituted the
basic opposition in the bourgeois world outlook since the origins of
the bourgeoisie. The current philosophical form of this world outlook: neo-positivism and its ‘spiritual complement’, existentialist-phenomenological subjectivism. The variant peculiar to the Human Sciences: the ideology called ‘structuralist’;
– to conquer for science the majority of the Human
Sciences, above all, the Social Sciences, which, with exceptions, have
occupied as imposters the continent of History, the continent whose keys
Marx has given us;
– to develop the new science and philosophy with all
the necessary rigour and daring, linking them to the requirements and
inventions of the practice of revolutionary class struggle.
In theory, the decisive link at present: Marxist-Leninist philosophy.
5 You have said two apparently contradictory
or different things : 1. philosophy is basically political ; 2.
philosophy is linked to the sciences. How do you conceive this double
relationship?
Here again I shall give my answer in the form of schematic and provisional theses.
1. The class positions in confrontation in the class struggle are ‘represented’ in the domain of practical ideologies (religious, ethical, legal, political, aesthetic ideologies) by world outlooks
of antagonistic tendencies: in the last instance idealist (bourgeois)
and materialist (proletarian). Everyone had a world outlook
spontaneously.
2. World outlooks are represented in the domain of theory (science + the ‘theoretical’ ideologies which surround science and scientists) by philosophy. Philosophy represents the class struggle in theory. That is why philosophy is a struggle (Kampf said Kant), and basically a political struggle: a class struggle. Everyone is not a philosopher spontaneously, but everyone may become one.
3. Philosophy exists as soon as the theoretical domain exists: as soon as a science (in the strict sense) exists. Without sciences, no philosophy, only world outlooks. The stake in the battle and the battle-field must be distinguished. The ultimate stake of philosophical struggle is the struggle for hegemony between the two great tendencies in world outlook (materialist and idealist). The main
battlefield in this struggle is scientific knowledge: for it or against
it. The number-one philosophical battle therefore takes place on the
frontier between the scientific and the ideological. There the idealist
philosophies which exploit the sciences struggle against the materialist
philosophies which serve the sciences. The philosophical struggle is a
sector of the class struggle between world outlooks. In the past,
materialism has always been dominated by idealism.
4. The science founded by Marx has changed the whole situation in the theoretical domain. It is a new
science: the science of history. Therefore, for the first time ever, it
has enabled us to know the world outlooks which philosophy represents
in theory; it enables us to know philosophy. It provides the means to
transform the world outlooks (revolutionary class struggle conducted
according to the principles of Marxist theory). Philosophy is therefore
doubly revolutionized. Mechanistic materialism, ‘idealistic in history’,
becomes dialectical materialism. The balance of forces is reversed: now
materialism can dominate idealism in philosophy, and, if the political
conditions are realized, it can carry the class struggle for hegemony
between world outlooks.
Marxist-Leninist philosophy, or dialectical materialism, represents the proletarian class struggle in theory. In the union of Marxist theory and the Workers’ Movement (the ultimate
reality of the union of theory and practice) philosophy ceases, as Marx
said, to ‘interpret the world’. It becomes a weapon with which ‘to
change it’: revolution.
6 Are these the reasons which have made you say that it is essential to read Capital today?
Yes. It is essential to read and study Capital.
– in order really to understand, in all its scope
and all its scientific and philosophical consequences, what proletarian
militants have long understood in practice: the revolutionary character
of Marxist theory.
– in order to defend that theory against all the
bourgeois and petty-bourgeois interpretations, i.e. revisions, which
seriously threaten it today: in the first place the opposition
Economism/Humanism.
– in order to develop Marxist theory and produce the
scientific concepts indispensable to the analysis of the class struggle
today, in our countries and elsewhere.
It is essential to read and study Capital. I
should add, it is necessary, essential to read and study Lenin, and all
the great texts, old and new, to which has been consigned the
experience of the class struggle of the international Workers’ Movement.
It is essential to study the practical works of the Revolutionary
Workers’ Movement in their reality, their problems and their
contradictions: their past and, above all, their present history.
In our countries there are immense resources for the
revolutionary class struggle today. But they must be sought where they
are: in the exploited masses. They will not be ‘discovered’ without
close contact with the masses, and without the weapons of
Marxist-Leninist theory. The bourgeois ideological notions of
‘industrial society’, ‘neo-capitalism’, ‘new working class’, ‘affluent
society’, ‘alienation’ and tutti quanti are anti-scientific and anti-Marxist: built to fight revolutionaries.
I should therefore add one further remark: the most important of all.
In order really to understand what one ‘reads’ and
studies in these theoretical, political and historical works, one must
directly experience oneself the two realities which determine
them through and through: the reality of theoretical practice (science,
philosophy) in its concrete life; the reality of the practice of revolutionary class struggle
in its concrete life, in close contact with the masses. For if theory
enables us to understand the laws of history, it is not intellectuals,
nor even theoreticians, it is the masses who make history. It
is essential to learn with theory – but at the same time and crucially,
it is essential to learn with the masses.
7 You attach a great deal of importance to rigour, including a rigorous vocabulary. Why is that?
A single word sums up the master function of philosophical practice: ‘to draw a dividing line’ between the true ideas and false ideas. Lenin’s words.
But the same word sums up one of the essential operations in the direction of the practice of class struggle: ‘to draw a dividing line’ between the antagonistic classes. Between our class friends and our class enemies.
It is the same word. A theoretical dividing
line between true ideas and false ideas. A political dividing line
between the people (the proletariat and its allies) and the people’s
enemies.
Philosophy represents the people’s class struggle in theory. In return it helps the people to distinguish in theory and in all ideas
(political, ethical, aesthetic, etc.) between true ideas and false
ideas. In principle, true ideas always serve the people; false ideas
always serve the enemies of the people.
Why does philosophy fight over words? The realities
of the class struggle are ‘represented’ by ‘ideas’ which are
‘represented’ by words. In scientific and philosophical reasoning, the
words (concepts, categories) are ‘instruments’ of knowledge. But in
political, ideological and philosophical struggle, the words are also
weapons, explosives or tranquillizers and poisons. Occasionally, the
whole class struggle may be summed up in the struggle for one word
against another word. Certain words struggle amongst themselves as
enemies. Other words are the site of an ambiguity: the stake in a
decisive but undecided battle.
For example : Communists struggle for the suppression of classes
and for a communist society, where, one day, all men will be free and
brothers. However, the whole classical Marxist tradition has refused to
say that Marxism is a Humanism. Why? Because practically, i.e. in the facts,
the word Humanism is exploited by an ideology which uses it to fight,
i.e. to kill, another, true, word, and one vital to the proletariat: the
class struggle.
For example : revolutionaries know that, in the last instance,
everything depends not on techniques, weapons, etc., but on militants,
on their class consciousness, their devotion and their courage. However,
the whole Marxist tradition has refused to say that it is ‘man’ who makes history. Why? Because practically, i.e. in the facts,
this expression is exploited by bourgeois ideology which uses it to
fight, i.e. to kill another, true, expression, one vital for the
proletariat: it is the masses who make history.
At the same time, philosophy, even in the lengthy
works where it is most abstract and difficult, fights over words:
against lying words, against ambiguous words; for correct words. It
fights over ‘shades of opinion’.
Lenin said: ‘Only short-sighted people can consider
factional disputes and a strict differentiation between shades of
opinion inopportune or superfluous. The fate of Russian Social-Democracy
for very many years to come may depend on the strengthening of one or
the other “shade.”’ (What is to be Done?).
The philosophical fight over words is a part of the
political fight. Marxist-Leninist philosophy can only complete its
abstract, rigorous and systematic theoretical work on condition that it
fights both about very ‘scholarly’ words (concept, theory, dialectic,
alienation, etc.) and about very simple words (man, masses, people,
class struggle).
No comments:
Post a Comment